PBP - Part 2: The Treaty of Game Theory

Mar. 12, 2025
By:
Jeremy Flores
Amber Durrell

Push Button Putsch Series

Introduction: The “Brain Trusters” 01. Models of Change 02. The Treaty of Game Theory 03. The Lights of Perverted Science Bibliography

Thomas Mann wrote on the allure of force to fascists:

fascism [] has deep and perhaps indestructible roots in human nature; for its essence is force .... [Force] can accomplish everything, or practically everything. Once it has subjugated the body through fear, it can even subjugate thought. For man in the long run cannot live a double life in order to live in harmony with himself, he adapts his thoughts to the manner of life that force imposes upon him. All this force can accomplish.1

But, he also observed a competing aspect of human experience:

The idea is a specific and essential attribute of man, that which makes him human. It is within him a real and natural fact, so impossible of neglect that those who do not respect human nature’s participation in the ideal—as force certainly does not—commit the clumsiest and, in the long run, the most disastrous mistakes.2

The deliberative fascist project we are facing now is not yet as elementally “forceful” as the mid-century fascist movements. Indeed there is rudimentary “participation in the ideal” (which we here take to mean, without loss of Mann’s intent, higher grades of actuality above the obviously material); the problem now is subtler, lying in particular in the degree of “respect” for “human nature’s participation” in the ideal. The twentieth-century dispute was more obvious: the level of “respect,” as Mann suggests, was at or near zero in favor of the human faculty of “force.” In our current period, we are dealing not with the specter of “force” but with that of advantage. Advantage is a shade more abstract and requires a slightly higher order of ability compared to the exertion of mere “force,” but it remains at the animal level and below the highest abilities exclusively accessible to humans—such as reasoning. Our military victory in the Second World War met force with force but failed to solve the problem of humanity’s degeneration to reliance on force itself either by way of the actualization of it or by way of the threat of the actualization of it by those with dominative advantage, and the problem has returned having learned to wear a suit.3

Far from creating a new-and-improved, less-impulsive form of fascism as some hoped, shifting to a frame of advantage instead of overt force does nothing to redeem the ideology. Advantage held by one person is necessarily contingent upon the disadvantage of one or more others. And, unlike those who can traffic in more sophisticated conceptual entities, purist advantage-seekers have no compensatory facility with the “complex of an indivisible kind, freighted with spirituality and elementary dynamic force”4 which exists among conceptual entities such as “truth,” “freedom,” and “justice”: that is, the realms approaching the “absolute.”5

Advantage is a shade more abstract and requires a slightly higher order of ability compared to the exertion of mere “force,” but it remains at the animal level and below the highest abilities exclusively accessible to humans—such as reasoning.

More concretely, the new fascist interpretive system is built explicitly upon a single relation between two members: “has advantage over,” as in “x has advantage over y.” Game theory and its pursuit of game-theoretic “rationality”—that is, of optimality of advantage—may therefore be seen as a calculus of advantage and, in this light, is a rather obviously inadequate system by which to model all of human society. At best, a higher order of thinking is required to wield game-theoretic concerns for the purpose of universally6 containing the various instabilities that arise from excessive pursuits of advantage toward equilibrium; by extent, the Hayekian denialism of higher orders, of course, makes this an impossibility, leaving a naïve pursuit of advantage to be the “natural law” of the land. The actually-natural rule of the jungle—which is to say that which is concealed behind Hobbes’ “civil law”—must eventually follow, especially if these pseudo-intellectal trends in thought are to become a truly-global orthodoxy.

The Italian fascist Julius Evola, whose work is resurgent in Silicon Valley and other far-right circles,7 provides a clear description of how an advantage-based society that denies subtler conceptual entities is highly compatible with aristocracy. As he writes:

The Gospel principle of returning good for evil is not for aristocrats: they may pardon and be generous, but only to a vanquished enemy, not to one still standing in all the force of his injustice. Nor is love an aristocratic principle, in the sense of a need to embrace, commune with, and take care of those who may not even want or deserve it. Relations between aristocratic equals have nothing communistic or fraternal about them: they are facts of loyalty, recognition, mutual respect, with each keeping his own dignity distinct. For this reason there is nothing in the hierarchy of the [aristocratic] warrior caste8 resembling a “mystic” bond, an incorporeal and impersonal dependency.9


We may take the current manifestation of the fascist problem to be a type of aristocracy rebranded in the language of mathematics that flirts with overt force via technology, but generally is more deliberative than the previous iteration. From this lens, is Mann’s observation that, “in the long run, the most disastrous mistakes” will necessarily occur still guaranteed? We see that they no longer “commit the clumsiest” errors as, indeed, they have advanced to the point of capturing the United States federal government and threatening all democracies globally. We must first understand that each action they take is because it follows from an advantageous strategy, i.e. that all judgments and commitments stem from not only material gain but from material advantage; the former facilitating the latter rather than being only an end itself.

Now comes the critical question: is an advantageous strategy necessarily a winning strategy? To answer this, we note two considerations. The first is that the pursuit of an unchecked naïve advantage must lead to an unstable Silicon Valley-style boom-and-bust cycle across all of society that itself is easy to game by those with advantage,10 indicating an unstable and tiresome system that quickly spins out to the failure state of oligarchy. The second is that from advantage comes a kind of egoic, manic ambition, a uniquely-human attribute which would be a key characteristic motivating those seeking a Kulturmission or, grander still, an “ecumenical” ideological project. More specifically, an egoically-ambitious strategy could be said to be a peculiarly advantage-maximizing one that addicts the individual who has adopted it in two easily-measurable ways: first by the degree of advantage held over others, second by the total number of people over which advantage is had. A cancer-like solipsistic game with no end, exit, or proper contextualization, the strategy eventually destroys itself, is destroyed by the healthy, or destroys that which sustains it—thereby destroying itself and everything else. These are the three outcomes available to us now that we find ourselves in this situation. Interestingly, given the addictive quality of the ideology, whether the new fascists have chosen a winning strategy is out of their control.

Each action they take is because it follows from an advantageous strategy, i.e. that all judgments and commitments stem from not only material gain but from material advantage; the former facilitating the latter rather than being only an end itself.

The ambitious should not be congratulated for not falling back to a violent strategy because what they are doing is worthy of no particular respect, and yet worship of and deference to the game-theoretically “rational,” nevertheless, is common in our society. The “rationally” ambitious simply have slightly greater mental faculty compared to their predecessors such that they do not immediately reach for violence, but, were they in a disadvantageous position, they may very well appeal to it just the same. In fact, where the merely violent seek to “subjugate[] the body through fear” and, from there, “even subjugate thought,”11 the ambitious, capable of the slightly-more abstract, seek, as Theory of Games “teaches,” to “convinc[e] [] the interested parties [based] upon the physical facts of the situation—in the terminology of games, on the rules of the game.”12 The ambitious have advanced only insofar as they merely continually threaten and imply violence rather than overtly wield it, and thus their “subjugat[ion]” is conducted by means of inference, a kind of special language of savviness among the “rational” actors (which, it must be noted, allows them to make special deals among themselves particularly benefitting their individual persons as this, too, is “rational”; this being one means by which a special “classification” among humans may be bestowed towards the goal of imposing hierarchy). The violent and the naïvely ambitious ultimately share the same underlying motive, and in fact the same “terminus technicus13 may be used: domination.14

Needless to say, the modal shifting among various means of “subjugat[ion]” is hardly an advance in civilization: rather, it is a mere detente, at best a means by which an aristocratic coalition may form to exert domination over everyone else in a partitioned fashion. The mid-century conflict, then, was hardly resolved. Ferdinand Foch, commander of all allied forces during WWI, had reportedly stated that the Treaty of Versailles “is not Peace. It is an Armistice for twenty years.” Similarly, the Treaty of Game Theory could be seen as an armistice formulated by the “brain trusters,” eventually allowing for the recurrence of fascism by any or all of the theory’s shortcomings, of the theory’s underexamined precepts, or of explicit design; its eighty-year lifespan accounted for by the slightly-more abstract mechanisms at play. The apparent entente is over: the threat of the use of nuclear weapons in the Ukraine conflict empirically shows that even the doctrine of mutually-assured destruction is failing (or, more cynically, has served its purpose: the USSR adopting the doctrine could also be seen as a significant advancement of an “ecumenical”-scale Kulturmission).15

Now comes the critical question: is an advantageous strategy necessarily a winning strategy?

To the new-form ambitious fascist, then, “respect [for] human nature’s participation in the ideal” is at best middling; thus, to them, having “respect” for subtler forms of the “ideal”—such as wisdom, intellectual honesty, or a great many other elements present in or consequent of the higher grades of thought—would result in a disadvantageous strategy since their proper adoption would naturally delimit material gain and material advantage. And from this, we can explain much: for example, the little-publicized rule among the securely positioned, “Don’t move unless you have to,” is simply that the advantage is already had by the accumulation of excess resources, thus the change occurs from making decisions which maximize advantage to making decisions which minimize the risk of disadvantage and loss.16

Now, critically, this particular behavior, this act of stillness, may appear to the untrained eye as strikingly similar to that borne out of intelligence, but we must not mistake one for the other: judgment is the product of intelligence, whereas mere decision is the product of calculation;17 the actually intelligent are purposeful in action in all cases, whereas the advantage oriented are only cautious in action when advantage is already achieved and secured.18 Many have come to believe that elites are necessarily intelligent and are necessarily imbued with good judgment, but anyone who has met the full brat pack of any elite parent would find among them a disparity of intelligence no different than would be found anywhere else. From such an observation, one may immediately understand that there is absolutely nothing biologically inherent to their success; rather, what distinguishes them from any other family are the commonalities of composure, calm, and other surficial appearances of what many assume follow from intelligence.

Niebuhr, in fact, shows that European languages going back to Ancient Greek possess an “aristocratic confusion of manners and morals”19 where a single term, such as “gentleman” or “nobleman,” connotes a panoply of positive characteristics possessed by such a person, e.g. that they are simultaneously or interchangeably “well-born,” “well-mannered,” “virtuous,” and “considerate.” Mere adherence to manners, it must be emphasized, is in no way a sign of possession of intelligence or of morals but rather is a signifier that one knows how to adhere to “the rules of the game”; that is, the facility for advantage must be held to be conceptually distinct from the rest of a person’s abilities to be able to truly evaluate the quality of a person, otherwise intellect, morality, manners, aristocracy, ambition, and advantage-seeking are gummed together into a confusing bundle.

Judgment is the product of intelligence, whereas mere decision is the product of calculation; the actually intelligent are purposeful in action in all cases, whereas the advantage oriented are only cautious in action when advantage is already achieved and secured.

Coming back to Evola, he explicitly appeals to surficial appearance when he states that the “ideal aristocrat or gentleman” possesses “composure and conscious equilibrium that is both ‘style’ and ‘rule’.” Even more, he believes that this “style” “is also found in the description of figures like the Greek sage, the Buddhist ascetic, or the Perfect Man of the Far East.”20

That is, to the Evolans, the aristocrats not only possess the attributes of the warrior, but they also have those of the religious adherent and the great thinkers among the Ancient Greeks; is there anything the aristo can’t do? An egomaniacal ideology indeed!


The would-be aristocrats, perhaps, are the most confused of all since they have satisfied all the aching of their lower faculties, and yet all is hardly well in the world; the world, strangely, does not celebrate them at all. Let us now settle the matter. There is no “natural aristocracy,” and one never has, and never shall, exist: there is mere collusion among those who are well mannered, that is, those who know and gain from following “the rules of the game”; and the fact that most are mere participants in a game not of their own design pointedly suggests, for them, that there is not much to remark upon within their persons since, in the end, their “success” is fully contingent upon a particular ideological project whose fullest implications they likely do not understand, a project which they may not even be aware of at all.

Modern American elites, being commonly confused as possessing intelligence—or alternatively as possessing a notable “will”—have been rather exclusively granted the luxuries normally afforded to the actually intellectual (an even worse sin given that all persons should be given the same opportunities). With the continual erosion of an actual intellectual elite and the morally minded—such as has been facilitated by certain universities’ administrators—it is only the aristocratic elite, and they alone, who are now allowed to think, to strategize, to reflect, to watch, and to wait, all due to some “ineffable” quality they claim to possess (that is: sufficient financial independence and/or a willingness to serve various agendas towards the destruction not just of academia but of democracy itself). Everyone else—all the workers who carry out their orders and tasks, i.e. those whom the elite “brain” coordinates as a remote “body”21—must never pause as this is perceived as malfeasance or laziness; meaningless edicts from on high, such as “It’s Time to Build,” are issued, often to distract the populace from the undeniable problems our advantage-based22 system of organization manifesting in all corners. The acts of stillness—which also includes idleness, as Russell himself identifies23—are no longer affordances toward the betterment of society but are now undeservedly reserved for the elite and fetishized by everyone due to their artificially-created scarcity.

There is no “natural aristocracy,” and one never has, and never shall, exist: there is mere collusion among those who are well mannered, that is, those who know and gain from following “the rules of the game.”

Thus, the elite maintain an aura of superiority—that is, more “objectively” speaking, of being the exclusive beneficiaries of a supposedly-dominative solution—via possession of mere advantage and the comfort it provides, and from there they continually extend their trick to claim more and more authority where, in most cases, even an ounce of power vested in them was already an ounce too much. The new union of simple hedonistic, power-hungry elites and the more ideologically-charged fascists was sealed by a mutual commitment to advantage calculations as the means of organizing civilization.

As a sign of the near-elimination of an actual intelligentsia, the logical conclusion of this “terminus technicus” has perhaps come in the form of the man-child who has named his son “Techno Mechanicus”: Elon Musk. Given Elon’s particular interest in Mars, the name may be a reference to the miniature wargame Warhammer 40K which, according to its Fandom Wiki, has the “Adeptus Mechanicus,” i.e. the “Cult of the Machine based on Mars which provides the [galaxy-wide] Imperium with its scientists, engineers, and technicians.”24 “The tech-adepts of the Mechanicus,” the wiki goes on to state, “are the primary keepers of what is viewed as sacred wisdom, a privileged caste of Tech-priests who jealously guard the knowledge required to maintain and construct much of the Imperium’s advanced technology.” The lore goes on: “The religion Cult Mechanicus values knowledge and the technology it creates above all else and views the final embrace of technology in the form of a purely mechanical existence as the ultimate destiny for Mankind’s evolution.”25 Warhammer fans have noticed the comparison themselves; though, even if it is pure coincidence, that itself points to the utter nonsense that spews forth from our dear leaders. Names, plans, projects that first and foremost appear to the untrained eye as strikingly similar to those borne out of intelligence but, in actuality, originate from variations of mere “positive thinking” at best; and at worst, from a computer via AI slop or, given that our rulers’ “thinking” is closer to AI system than many may care to admit, from an actual human mind that can only produce a slop-like discharge.26

The new union of simple hedonistic, power-hungry elites and the more ideologically-charged fascists was sealed by a mutual commitment to advantage calculations as the means of organizing civilization.

According to our new rulers, all is fair in Lovecraft and Warhammer: “Turn[ing] the White House Lawn into a Tesla Showroom,” apartheid, Sieg Heils from behind the Presidential Seal, buying (or even possibly rigging) elections, destroying democracy, dismantling the international order, not to mention all manner of wackadoodle beliefs and ideologies such as the summoning of “xenodemons” and “egregores” into your pocket calculator. None of it needs to make sense: the aristocrat is exempted from such outmoded concerns.

It seems that an integral part of Too Big To Fail 2.0 is Grift 2.0: where the scams of old were conducted by knowing confidence men upon sucker victims, in the age of information the fraudsters themselves are now at least as confused as their marks, and what they sell are not even dreams anymore but bare delusions. Now that Mars and beyond are incessantly promised, the sky is no longer the limit: all that is required is becoming detached from reality.


  1. Mann, The Coming Victory of Democracy, p. 16-17.
  2. Mann, The Coming Victory of Democracy, p. 18.
  3. This, no less than his wit, may help explain the fashionable rise of Derek Guy, an unlikely public figure who reminds us of how ill-fitting those suits are on the original fascists’ successors. Hugo Boss is likely rolling in his grave.
  4. Mann, The Coming Victory of Democracy, p. 19.
  5. Mann argues that such concepts are “indivisible.” We amend this to instead view the general human process as one progressing toward the absolute, in part by having rationalistic understanding of increasingly-subtler concepts; that is, a rich, coherent system of strongly-distinguished conceptual entities and accompanying relations among them. Thus, Mann’s “complex” as stated should not be viewed as forever “indivisible,” and, regarding the particular concepts he identifies, the general task before us at this point in time is to rationally divide, order, and interrelate them. Also, by no means would such an accomplishment be an “end of history”: as a result of such a process, new, still-subtler concepts inadequately distinguished will doubtless present themselves; advancement proceeds.
  6. That is, without division of the human population into tiers or hierarchies, “naturally” justified or otherwise.
  7. Take, for example, Dryden Brown, cofounder of Praxis Nation, a charter city project backed by Peter Thiel, Sam Altman’s investment firm, the Winklevoss twins, and Sam Bankman-Fried’s now-defunct Alameda Research. According to multiple former employees, “Brown encouraged staff to read the work of Julius Evola ... [and] one witnessed him dress down staffers after someone left a copy of Evola’s Ride the Tiger where it might be spotted by visitors .... Brown also kept a private collection of ‘bad books,’ as one of those former staffers described them, that he would only share with someone he thought was likely to be on the same ideological page.”

    (Also, see: Series Introduction, fn. 4.)
  8. Earlier in the chapter, Evola states that the “aristocratic ideal ... [is] chiefly linked to a tradition of the warrior type,” i.e. Evola unjustifiably attempts to imbue the aristo with the characteristics of the warrior. Given that Thiel’s Founders Fund is a significant investor in Anduril, it is perhaps worth comparing Evola’s thoughts with Palmer Luckey’s recent statement where he talks about the need for a “warrior class” of which he considers himself a member. See: Series Introduction.
  9. Evola, Introduction to Magic, Vol. 3, p. 97.
  10. See the canonical example of the US stock market or, more recently, the “rug pulls” that are part and parcel with nearly the entirety of the cryptocurency system which our president and First Lady now participate in.
  11. Mann, The Coming Victory of Democracy, p. 17.
  12. Von Neumann, Theory of Games, p. 37.
  13. Von Neumann, Theory of Games, p. 37.
  14. In yet another flourish of linguistic trickery (see the Game Theory section in Models of Change), von Neumann and Morgenstern reject the term “superior” to signify comparison of better or worse game solutions because of “its manifold associations” and, in its place, instead use the term “domination.” Thus, we can again see the workings of the slightly-more abstract mind: it is not the agent who dominates another, but rather the rules of the game itself suggest a dominating strategy; a plausible-enough shift from “subjectivity” to “objectivity” except, of course, for the fact that the strategies are exercised by and are applied upon actual persons (though soldier automation removes even the human applicators from the equation, making such use of force doubly “objective” since all strategies and their executions are without persons that can be “blamed” for an excess of “subjectivity”).

    The “ecumenical” game-theoretic “good society,” in other words, does not require superior or inferior ranking of persons or groups, such as races, ethnicities, genders, socioeconomic strata, etc.; though, as we have all seen by living in—being subjected to—this “good society,” it is hardly precluded. In fact, Theory of Games formally defines the mechanism of “discrimination” where a group of agents ”assign to [another agent] the amount which he gets” and, therefrom, split the disproportionate proceeds among themselves: for the “excluded player [who] is absolutely ‘tabu,’” that agent’s “place in society [] is prescribed by the [] other players; he is excluded from all negotiations that may lead to coalitions. Such negotiations do go on, however, [among] the [] other players.” (Von Neumann, Theory of Games, p. 289. Emphasis in original.)

    The supposed advancement—the supposed universality achieved—is nothing more than the adjustment of terminology first and foremost combined with a de-emphasis on inherent qualities of superiority, emphasizing in its place which person—or group—possesses the ability to dominate all other persons and groups. When actually applied in the concrete world, this must take into account the given actual situations of the actual agents, which is to say that the adoption of such a doctrine at a given point in time must necessarily be applied to agents with highly-variable starting conditions, internationally by the immediate results of the Second World War, domestically by preceding racialist policies. In this way the dominant US postwar position was translated into international hegemony, while internal to the country an implicit supremacist policy was formulated where certain groups, with comparatively-poorer starting conditions, are logically determined—rather than inherently determined—to be inferior based on the “objective” valuation of their overall performance—their “ability to compete”—in society; which is to say determined of deeply-flawed logic.

    This perspective, of course, can lead to, and has led to, atrocities being committed both internally and abroad, a natural consequence when a person or group fails to be logically “convinc[ed]” by “the physical facts of the situation” into a submissive role; and, further, von Neumann’s “proposal of a lunchtime nuke over Moscow” may be fully understood, and whatever debate there is about his intention when making such statements may be laid to rest.
  15. If mutually-assured destruction was indeed intended to extend an “ecumenical” Kulturmission, then what we are experiencing now may be seen as its still-further extension as the coalition proceeds; or perhaps even as the Eastern countermove against the West exercised by way of co-optation of such a coalition.
  16. The shift to game theory in global affairs—that is, the shift from actual violence to the threat of actual violence—is more clearly understood by way of analytic-philosophical devices: they introduced the logical contingency, rather than logical necessity, of violence which itself is dictated by the (supposed) logical necessity afforded by some given game-theoretic analysis. In this way, the inadequacy is quite apparent: the ground of necessity is itself dictated by “the physical facts of the situation” which are actually extremely-contingent facts; any random person or group, especially over time, can come into possession of dominative “physical facts,” especially when weapons of mass destruction exist. This framework is more “might makes right” than anything approaching civility: that is, it is of a naïvely-physicalist philosophy and therefore is victim to the accompanying weaknesses, in this case hidden behind mathematization.

    The doctrine of mutually-assured destruction likewise had presumed safeties in place: a disciplined international order—that is, a set of states run by “rational” leaders—which itself is predicated upon a global stability from a stable climate and, from these, sufficient control over the creation and ownership of such weapons was presumed to be had. With these givens removed, the doctrine is invalidated (even more so by the pursuit of a “multipolar” world which threatens not only proliferation but ready and wanton exercise). That is, the presumption of the “rational” actor is also invalidated since “the physical facts of the situation” of global instability imply that control over who gets to be a player becomes increasingly untenable over time. In other words, their enjoyment of “discrimination”—a key factor in the doctrine of mutually-assured destruction which, via its centrality, is also used to excuse other discriminatory acts in society—is imperiled as a greater and more unpredictable variety of players will likely manifest.

    This could be a key motive for soldier automation: global oppression to limit access to weapons of mass destruction, thereby preserving the “dominative” solution benefitting the “rational” actors by guaranteeing “the physical facts of the situation” and, from there, also guaranteeing their advantage during an unstable period; death en masse acceptable so long as it is delivered by the appropriate means, the button pushed by the appropriate hands.
  17. If one is led to believe that governance is merely decision theoretic—of supposed rationality but exclusive of the higher, less-discretized elements of intelligence—then of course one would be led to believe that representative government is outmoded and that it can be fully automated. This, however, obviously removes the key entity of redress from a system which, in the United States’ case, was guaranteed since our government is “of the people, by the people, for the people,” as Lincoln stated at the end of his Gettysburg Address, emphasizing, in fact, that it “shall not perish from the Earth”; quite a statement given the years of bloodshed that had just transpired, and doubtless a warning to posterity.

    This horrific potential outcome was also warned against by Arendt: “the latest and perhaps most formidable form of [] domination: bureaucracy or the rule of an intricate system of bureaus in which no men, neither one nor the best, neither the few nor the many, can be held responsible, and which could be properly called rule by Nobody .... [W]e identify tyranny as government that is not held to give account of itself, [thus] rule by Nobody is clearly the most tyrannical of all, since there is no one left who could even be asked to answer for what is being done.” (Arendt, On Violence, p. 38-39.) (Here, one can easily replace “bureau” with “algorithm” to update the means by which “rule by Nobody” may be achieved, e.g. “an intricate system of algorithms in which no men ... can be held responsible.“)

    In an interview, Arendt also gives us an idea of what the true purpose of the proliferation of AI slop—and the necessarily-consequential degradation of permanent, immutable fact itself—is: “If everybody always lies to you, the consequence is not that you believe the lies, but rather that nobody believes anything any longer. This is because lies, by their very nature, have to be changed, and a lying government has constantly to rewrite its own history. On the receiving end you get not only one lie—a lie which you could go on for the rest of your days—but you get a great number of lies, depending on how the political wind blows. And a people that no longer can believe anything cannot make up its mind. It is deprived not only of its capacity to act but also of its capacity to think and to judge. And with such a people you can then do what you please.”

    In this way, the modern fascists’ strategy to “subjugate thought,” as Mann wrote, involves attacking everyone’s “capacity to think and to judge” by algorithmically destroying both access to and the importance of fact, truth, consistency, actual rationalistic evaluation, and more. Such is the end state of the “information age.”
  18. This is historically known as the sin of sloth.
  19. Niebuhr, Moral Man and Immoral Society, p. 172.
  20. Evola, Introduction to Magic, Vol. 3, p. 91.
  21. The guillotine, then, possesses great symbolic meaning to all involved both in its threat and in its occasional utilization: the brains supposedly so great as to manage the world itself, in the end, were unable to protect their own bodies from the ol’ slice-and-dice, a device which relieves them of the burden of the maintenance of all bodies, be it personal, governmental, or public.

    This, perhaps, explains our earlier observation about Jack Clark, a cofounder of Anthropic, who had tweeted that “[p]eople don’t take guillotines seriously. Historically, when a tiny group gains a huge amount of power and makes life-altering decisions for a vast number of people, the minority gets, actually, for real, killed. People feel like this can’t happen anymore.”

    The fact that he more recently appealed to the postmodern Pontypool-esque scatlang of neoreactionary figure Nick Land is certainly a curious decision given his stated worries, especially given the numerous references in the latter’s work to neo-occult concepts such as “xenodemons” and “egregores” which, Land and his followers believe, may soon manifest or may have already manifested into our existence via technical systems such as the internet and those found in current AI approaches. As Clark writes on his blog: “AI is an acausal creature from the future hijacking the present” then goes on to quote a passage from Land which states that we are undergoing “an invasion from the future by an artificial intelligent space that must assemble itself entirely from its enemy’s resources.”

    He ends this passage with a striking comment about his own free will, suggesting that he, in fact, is slave to this future “xenodemon” (and from that, he presumably believes that he should be considered exempt from those guillotines he is so worried about): “Why this matters – how much agency do we really have about the development of AI? These days, I struggle a lot with agency. How much agency do you have over a technology when, to use a phrase regularly uttered by Ilya Sutskever, AI technology ‘wants to work’?” (Emphasis in original.)

    In Land’s and Clark’s thinking, would-be aristos can keep their privileged social positions while also achieving Arendt’s aforementioned “rule by Nobody” simply by having the “Nobody” be the “xenodemon,” i.e. according to them, we are, and perhaps always have been, ruled by a figment of pure imagination. More specifically, the “xenodemon” is probably an authoritative personification or anthropomorphization of their beliefs about futurism and technology; again, there is an addictive quality in their ideology, and things are now out of their control.

    This bizarre, fantastic Lovecraftian belief system may have received general uptake among the elite; if, from there, it is informing their governance decisions, then everyone indeed has much to worry about, not least due to potential commitments to advancing such a fictive project rather than, for example, actual projects like reversing climate change. Unfortunately, fiction seems to be the course that is set as “Trump’s FBI Moves to Criminally Charge Major Climate Groups.”
  22. To be more exact, we are referring to the problems engendered by the Genevans’ greater “praxeological” system of “thinking” which includes von Neumann’s and Morgenstern’s game theory as one of its cornerstones, i.e. VNM’s work has been positioned as a proper subset of a very particular—and very-philosophically radical—ideological project. We will examine this in greater detail in future articles.
  23. E.g. “those whose work was demanded were made to work long hours, and the rest were left to starve as unemployed. Why? because work is a duty, and a man should not receive wages in proportion to what he has produced, but in proportion to his virtue as exemplified by his industry. This is the morality of the Slave State, applied in circumstances totally unlike those in which it arose. No wonder the result has been disastrous.” (Russell, In Praise of Idleness, p. 6.)
  24. Why might Elon try to manifest science fiction into reality? Palmer Luckey, another tech industrialist, gives a pragmatic possibility: “One of the things that I’ve realized in my career is that nothing I ever come up with will be new. I’ve literally never come up with an idea that a science fiction author has not come up with before.”

    However, an answer also can be found in the aforementioned work of Nick Land, namely his concept of “hyperstition,” which, according to Land, “is a positive feedback circuit including culture as a component. It can be defined as the experimental (techno-)science of self-fulfilling prophecies. Superstitions are merely false beliefs, but hyperstitions—by their very existence as ideas—function causally to bring about their own reality. Capitalist economics is extremely sensitive to hyperstition, where confidence acts as an effective tonic, and inversely.” It is a sort of “power of positive thinking” but, where Peale, the actual author of The Power of Positive Thinking, emphasized “the primacy of thought over matter, the power of intention, and the ability of individuals through proper mental and spiritual hygiene to channel an infinitely powerful reservoir of creative cosmic energy,” (Baker, Make Your Own Job, p. 197) Land instead goes with a basis of Deleuze, (techno-)tulpas, and an outdated ’90s cyberpunk aesthetic.

    Hypercapitalism and the far right, however, are threaded through both: Peale “railed from the pulpit against Roosevelt[], the labor movement[], and secularism[]. His behind-the-scenes political activity was just as significant” as he once appeared at a rally alongside “a far-right backer of Francisco Franco” as well as an “antisemitic ‘radio priest.’” (Baker, Make Your Own Job., p. 196-197.) Even more, Peale was a great personal influence on Donald Trump and officiated his first two marriages, suggesting that our once-and-current king-president may be highly susceptible to such spurious lines of thinking.
  25. Given that, compare this with Vice President Vance’s comment regarding a recent SpaceX achievement: “I believe the destiny of this country is to conquer the stars.” Note that, in their vision, we are conquering—rather than exploring—the stars; since NASA just eliminated their chief scientist position, it is hard to disagree that a Warhammer-like future of interstellar war may be in their plans.
  26. We cannot trust that they can be reasoned with; but their belligerence can be dealt with via a number of vectors, some less obvious than others. As we have seen in the recent “Adrian Dittmann” livestream with Youtuber ConnorEatsPants, it may be that one solution is simply for the public (and, more carefully conducted, for the media) to endlessly and mercilessly bully these people.

    While our president just yesterday admonished the public that “you should cherish” Elon and that “we have to take care of our high-IQ people,” we must remember that Trump likely can provide only so many federal bailouts.